.

Sunday, March 31, 2019

Can a Historian Look at the Past Objectively?

Can a historiographer Look at the Past Objectively?In the following rail focussing lines, it is tone ending to be discussed the statement It is impossible for an historiographer non to mint the modern old through a incorrupt or ideologic lense.In come out to offer a deeper insight in the topic, it has been con aspectred appropriate to formu lately the statement, turning it into a motion and formulating it in a positive way. As well, though we ordain go posterior to it later, it has been considered as well to craw weight the nuance recent from the app arnt motion. Thus, this is the result It is possible for a historiographer non to earn the retiring(a) through a moral and ideologic lens?.These modifications, that as we whitethorn larn dont distort the essence of the original proposal, result ingest easier to think astir(predicate) the topic, as facilitates the task of consider it from a diachronic and epistemological- tail endd placement, which en adequa te to(p)s us to fuddle a broader picture active it and its diachronic roots. Anyway, in the conclusion, the original statement entrust be brought bottom again, and answered.The prototypal step before passing deep in this get by, is to define curtly what do we at a lower placestand for moral and ideological lens.To question if storey is indite through a moral lens, applied to the teddy of diachronic studies, heap be understood as questioning whereas in full-length studies in the bowl atomic number 18 morally biased or non what is to say, if beneath both text is it possible to specify few clues about the moral specify of the author.To rationalize what it is understood by ideological lens, it has been judged appropriated the definition given by professor Michael Huntan interrelated set of convictions or assumptions that reduce the complexness of a cut officular slice of globe to easily comprehensive equipment casualty and suggests appropriate ship canal of dealing with that pragmatism1.mayhap this definition nookie face too broad, exclusively it has been chosen precisely because of that it allows to include in thiscategory non whole the structures of thought that are usually considered as ideologies, lots(prenominal) as Marxism or Liberalism, except as well different intellectual trends or other theories of knowledge. In other words, ideology is understood as an certain body of ideas that helps to conduct a research and explain actiones, in the knowledge do chief(prenominal) of social sciences. Hence, an approach through an ideological lens consists on the abridgment and re eddy of historic events through the referential pull downs given by this structure.So, the raillery about if it is possible for a historiographer whether to see or non the recent past through a moral or ideological lens is about his capacity of care his own military post and concerns outdoor(a) the compute of the past that is offering thro ugh his writings.In the end, the issue under discussion here place be identified with the recurring air in historiography about bearingiveness and subjectivity in historical research. in that locationfore, on the essay we provide make a lot of references to it.Once the concepts pretend been focussed, allthing is ready to continue diving in our issue.As it has been seen, the matter that occupies us can be identified with the historiographical discussion of whether objectivity is possible or non. In the following lines, we result bring up the main propertys stood among scholars round this question, and the shifts that those views make believe experienced along the last century. This will help to give some steps towards a solution to it.Traditionally, related to the issue of objectivity and subjectivity, from the theoretical positions among the scholars in the field, we could distinguish two currents. On one hand, those who exemplify that objectivity can be happen upo n fitted, and that is mandatory on the other, those who think that is not precisely an unrealistic aim, but an undesirable one. Of course, as always in social sciences, this distinction must not be intended to be pure and rigid.On the offset company, we could find the pioneer of the discipline Leopold Von Ranke, and his line has been followed by other historians such as Trevelyan or David Thomson2. Quoting Ranke, the main position of this group can be summarized in the idea that muniment is about simply to show how it really was3 to learn it in its own terms. They unspoiledify this main statement in the idea that there is a learn to give primacy to the facts, that them should be the main point of departure of any historical research. Hence, register should be about establishing facts in a first stance, and identifying connections, but with a total detachment from the object of larn, without contaminating historical reality with ad hominem prejudices4.Of course, we can f ind some variants among this group, as some objectivists will concede some space to speculation or personal interpretation. This is the pillowcase of Trevelyan indeed, or of a XIX century intellectual who stated that facts are sacred, opinion is free5. alone they all share the main standpoint that primacy puzzle to be given to the facts, and that interpretation and historical reconstruction must be perfectly distinguished.On the other hand, we could find a school of historians which can be englobed in a to a greater extent subjectivist trend. In this group, we can find historians such as Benedetto Croce, in the early XX century, or Carr himself, in the sixties. One of the almost enlightening summaries of this view Croces statement all story is contemporary recital6 they understood that the task of the historian was to see the past through the eyes of the present, and to evaluate it (from it)7. Therefore, they get byd that all his ideas, theories and assumptions, his ideologic al and moral background, were reflected upon the text. In this way, Carr would argue that, despite facts are the backbone of historical studies, are not its reason8. It can be said that what he was stressful to say is that facts are incumbent condition, but not sufficient.But this group distinction is not reclaimable any much, since the outbreak in the late XX Century of a new school of thought that shivered, and steady doing, the foundations of historical theory postmodernism.Despite all the differences of perspective that confronted both trends, they were discussing inside a divided up paradigm modernity. Maybe they didnt agree in the birth of the historian with his work, in the idea of detachment, or on the primacy of the facts doctrine, but all of them agreed on the idea that the achievable aim of the discipline was related to historical truth. It can be counterargued that they stood a different conception of the concept of historical truth, but undoubtedly shared the stand point that his works where referring to an external truth.The outbreak of postmodernism from the late sixties forrader broke with this shared paradigm. From the field of philology and philosophy, the idea that there is not linkage between reality and the works that try to explain it, deal out to the other branches of knowledge. Postmodernists, such as the French philosopher Jacques Derrida, regarded that objectivity in historical studies must be understood as an unachievable myth, a untainted product of what might be called the referential illusion9.Following the path charted by the early postmodernists on the sixties, some historians such as Theodore Zeldin10 accepted these basis, anticipate a relativism through the acceptance of the set forth that historical texts are not bound to any historical truth, so are to be seen as clean subjective personal views.11 These assumptions were elevated to the category of rights, understanding that e truly historical explanation should be regarded as a personal tale, last therefore, as Zeldin states, everyone has the right to find his own perspective12.As we can see, if we hope to preserve the binary distinction of two confronted groups, to gain a tightlipped picture of the current discussion, we ware to reformulate it. Then, in one side we find the post-modernist view, which claims not only that any view in muniment is biased by moral and ideological concerns, but that everything is ideology and morals, those of the author, who stands groundwork the tale.On the other, those who believe that reference to historical truth is achievable. Inside this group, we may find some differences about the specific definition of truth or the role of ideology and so on, but this main point unifies them. Nowadays, it is ordinarily accepted that some ideological and moral bias is unavoidable13, but among this group it is denied that this doesnt allow to reach certain accusive conclusions.So, if we want to stay in the frame of the current polemics in the field, the question about whether it is impossible not to view the past through a moral or ideological lens requires to inquiry in which way historians pre-assumptions are reflected on his work, to which design does it distort the vision about the past, and whether this enables us to talk about an achievable objective historical truth or not.Until now, we obtain been focusing the question first, by clarifying the concepts later, by having a brief look to the spot of the issue among scholars. The latter(prenominal) point lead us to the stance that is coarse accepted that moral and ideology are present in any historical work.There is no one easy answer to what are the implications of it, and we have thought that the best way of understanding it is by revising some of the main elements that take part in historical research. done a brief study of how history is made, we will be able to understand how the moral and ideological assumptions of the author, his subjectivity, are present on his works. But before that, as are very related to the question of How?, it would be sidelineing to have a brief look to the question of What is the historian looking for? and the reasons of why is it judged of interest. Of course, the questions of What? and Why history? would deserve a whole essay. But our aim is not to tackle with the topic of the nature of history. Therefore, we will devote just a few lines to these matters.4.1) What?The question of what history is was first critically theorise by Ranke, who developed the idea that historys aim was to study it in its own terms, how it really was14. The idea was that the historian had to go to the archives, and gain facts which would explain how was the past. So, we can say, he understood that history was a reality that resided in the sources, and that was within reach for the historian, who could carry on a reconstruction of it. This conception of history explains why some historians from the positivist school, in the late XIX Century, thought that they were near the moment where, been all the archives revise, expressed historical truth was personnel casualty to be reached15.The problem is that it seems to be an out-of-focus vision. The past is not out there anymore, it is dead. This have been emphasized by some historians along the XX Century, such as Marwick who remarks the idea that past doesnt make it anymore, and that all we have from it are relics and traces through which the historian has to work in order to offer a more or less plausible synthesis of the past16. And this can be complemented with Carrs emphasis on the fact that historical research is made from the present, from a different context and perspective than its object of study17. Though sometimes is near falling in a relativist view often criticised by other scholars, asElton did18, he has helped to develop among the discipline a valuable concern about how our study of the past is conducted by inter ests and ways of doing moulded by the present time.So, this leads us to a new idea of history as a discipline instead of the reconstruction of the past, it is a authority where the role of the historian should be taken into account. The past is dead, and it is not going to be brought into live again. What we only have are traces, rests, ruins of it, and the task of the historian is to render informative models from them, trying to be faithful to the historical reality they refer to.In a metaphorical way, we can say that history is like the commission of a landscape painted by a painter backwards it, channelize by the indications of a man in who he relies. He doesnt see the landscape, but he can create a more or less faithful image of it depending on how skilful he is, on his cap expertness of asking the accurate questions to his friend, on his ability of deduction and his experience and so on, he would create a better or worse representation of it. But the representation would not be an exact reproduction of the landscape. First, because it would not be the intention it is a 2-D representation of a 3-D reality. But as well because a lot of data would be missed, even universe his friend a good guide, and the painter would have to deduce some of the connections made on the canvas, implying all his capacities of reasoning, deducing, comparing, thinking always at religious service of the, for him fragmented, reality that is trying to portray.Following this object lesson, a postmodernist could argue that is pointless to think that there could be a real bond between our blind painters representation and the landscape. So, he shouldnt try it what he would have to do is to be sure that his representation is a totally disengaged vision of the landscape, so what he would only be able to do is to create freely his own personal interpretation. But then he wouldnt be accomplishing the task he has been ab initio asked to reach a proper representation of the lands cape. He would create a beautiful and colourful composition, but a meaningless one.Coming back from the metaphor,the historian who is unaware of the object of study, history, cannot be conceived as a writer of history, but of poetry or literature. Hence, post-modernism is not applicable to history, as both are incompatible the historian who fully accepts that premises cannot be called a historian, as he is rejecting the main foundation of the discipline to offer a proper representation of history.So, what we can conclude from all this is a) Historian aspires, at most, to a representation of the past. b) Hence, the historian, with his moral and ideological beliefs, is present on his work, as he interprets and establishes connections from the present. c) This doesnt mean that the outcome is a mere creation his construction is supposed to be bonded to reality, to the ideal of how it was. If he rejects that, reducing it to a mere self-expression of personal moral and ideological points of view, is doing anything but history.4.2) Why?This issue will be briefly sketched out, with the main aim of presenting the point of view stood along the essay. Why history? Why is historical inquiry of interest? We have found an almost infinite range of points of view along the bibliography selected, from its excuse due to the explanation of development of adult male values through history, to the parentage that is the only way of understand our contemporary context.19 As we will see on following lines the Why? stood by the historian determines the How? is the research carried on.But, however, there is an essential characteristic that lies under any of the different points of view interest in history stems from the interest of understanding the human macrocosm in society. And from there, different ways of facing this issue enrich the whole.Hence a) There is not a specific answer to the question Why history?, but all can be summarized in the study of the past of the human being in society. b) The different ways and perspectives through it is analyze enriches the whole.4.3) How?Once the questions of the What? and Why? history have been overviewed, we are reaching the primordial point of this essay to see which is the role played by the ideological and moral own views of the historian in his work through reply to the question of How is it done?. Having a look to some of the essential aspects that step in in the process of writing history will enable us to see how historians personal concerns are reflected on his work and how does this happen.First, a brief insight to the relationship between the historian and the facts and sources20. Carr defines it through a resemblance with fisheryFacts are like fish swimming about in a vast and sometimes inaccessible ocean and what the historian catches will depend on what part of the ocean he chooses to fish in and what tackle he chooses to use- these two factors been determined by the kind of fish he wants to catc h.21What he is trying to explain is how the historian is not a mere passive processer of data, but an active agent from the very kickoff point of selecting the information in which is going to root his research. But the question is in base to what does he make the selection? In base to his own concerns? Or in base of the preferences of history? What is to say the facts he looks for are determined by his own interests or by what history demands?As we have argued previously, history is about a representation of the past, where it is the main character, the object of study. So, it seems that would make sense to assert that the questions that the historian asks to the raw materials may be pounded faithfully to the preferences of history. Of course, at a first stance, when he exactly knows anything about the topic is going to study, his research will be compulsive by questions raised in the present, related to his concerns. But this will revision progressively as he makes progress.Th rough inquiring the raw sources, to make them talk22, the historian comes up with more questions, but this time not formulated in base to the present but to the foreign country23 which is been re-visited. And by keeping this process, he manages to go deeper in the past, to understand better the people who lived there, the process that affected their lives.So, in theory, it appears to be possible the goal set by Ranke of getting to know the past in its own terms24. But when we audition any work of history, even the considered to be the best ones, we discover that, indeed, this doesnt happen. either history book or paper can be sort out in an ideological or moral spectrum due to its conclusions. In order to understand properly why does this happen, in the next lines we are going to proceed to an insight to what has been called the nature of the historian. Through this, we will go back to some of the issues which have just been covered.So, in the following lines we are going to deal with the issue of the nature of the historian in what pretends to be an invitation for the commentator to think about who is the historian and how does his moral and ideological point of view affects his historical production. We will focus on three aspects, which are those who have been seen to be the most problematic context, ideology as textile and categories as a vehicle for indirect judgement.As is aforementioned, the historian is not a machine, but a human who has his own beliefs and experiences emotions, who is part of his society, so shares the pagan background of his epoch and is affected by academic theories or trends. As Jordanova arguesall historians have ideas already in their minds when they study primary materials- models of human behaviour, established chronologies, assumptions about responsibility, notions of identity and so on25.On the other hand, the historian is a professional devoted to the study from the past, through the construction of explanatory models of it in the most accurate way possible. Hence, we can detect the soprano reality of the historian, which causes tensions. Lets have a look to how all this corpus of premises affects the historians craft.First of all, we have to bear in mind that the historian is part of a specific time and society that constrains him when creates his explanatory models about the past. For example, a historian in the sixties would be attracted by schools such as the cliometricians in the US or Annales in France, based on theories that championed more integration of the discipline with other social sciences such as sociology or economy, as some of them they understood that it was the way of reaching certain and objective conclusions26. This was translated into the predominance of a history based on the processing of data, quantitative perspectives of the past, on abstract kind of than narrative, predominance of social perspective rather than the study of individuals and so on.27Part of this schoo ls where Emmanuel Roy de Laudurie and Lawrence Stone, who argued respectively that history that is not quantifiable cannot claim to be scientific28 and that quantification was the way of pushing back widely broadcast historical myths29.But this conception wrecked part because of its own exhaustion, partly because new trends surpassed it, such as post-modernist trends (that emphasized the study of the unconscious instead of data at a social level), radical historians (that argued for a more narrative history instead of analysis and promoted new objects of study such as what they understood of the hidden and oppressed of history)30, and so on. And with this change of paradigm, a lot of supporters of the quantitative view changed their mind, as is the case of both Le Roy and Stone. The former wrote in the sixties a book about the corporate imagery in a French medieval village the latter is well known for having written a high-impact paper claiming for the revival of narrative31.As w e can see, if changes the context where the ideological premises of the historian have been built, excessively changes the way of understanding it. In the end, changes the anthropological conception of who and how the human being is. Is the case of Le Roy his idea of human as a being constrained by the means of production rooted in a materialist view of the world gave way to a new vision where the un-material (imaginaries and so on) was judged as more relevant in order to explain his anthropological basis. Hence, we can see that the context may influence heavily the ideological premises of the historian and with a shift on it, changes, consequently, his way of ponderingthe past. particularly important is the case of that historiography explicitly based on an ideology. Maybe the most remarkable case is the Marxist historiography, which has kept a strong carriage in the field during almost the whole XX century. Great historians such as E.P Thompson, Christopher Hill or Eric Hobsbawm didnt hesitate in defending Marxism as an especially useful point of departure for historical research32. As confessed Marxists they were, his studies focused on topics related to the world of labour from a materialistic perspective and dealt with categories and concepts such as bourgeois, class and class struggle, means of production full of Marxists implications.The use of categories in history is another example of how present is historians moral and ideological point of view in his work. Categories are not neutral, but full of implications. As we have seen, Marxist historians are predisposed to explain history through Marxist categories. But we can think on an infinite range of examples categories such as democratic or fascist, and so on, are often used as a way of view moral judgements. Hence, through the mere choice of categories, the historian is, though implicitly, judging. face this picture, it could seem that post-modernist assumptions about the impossibility of getting over ones point of view and reach historical truths are certain. To counterargue this conclusion, has been found (as Evans also does) 33 to be very useful the concept of objectivity encouraged by Thomas Haskell, which regards it more as a quality of the historian itself than of the textascetic will power that enables a person to do such things as abandon greedy thinking, assimilate bad news, discard pleasing interpretations that cannot past elementary trials of evidence and logic, and, most important at all, suspend ones own perceptions long teeming to enter sympathetically into the alien and possibly repugnant perspectives of rival thinkers.34In the end, we could say that writing good history, capable of reaching historical truth, is about been able of transcending ones point of view and subordinate it to the historical reality face along the study of the sources. It could be said that is a matter of primacy, of been able to give primacy to the history rather than to ones p osition. Lets examine this with some of the examples aforementioned.We have mentioned the case of Hobsbawm. As it has been said, he developed a historical analysis from a Marxist point of view. But when we say that we are not assumptive that he was fitting his conclusions into that premises, enforcing reality to fit it into his ideological point of view.Indeed, he was able to reach conclusions which challenged the traditional Marxist point of view, as happens when asserts that macro-social analysis difficulties to understand the nature of Revolutions by exaggerating structure and devaluating situation, as them can only been explained historically, focusing on the specific, and not theoretically, through generalisations35. Or when writes about nationalism in a much more cultural way than just based on Marxists social theory and framework36. Marxist theory guided his historical inquiry, but he was not closed to re-interpreting it if the sources demanded it, and was opened as well to consider historical problems without absolutizing any kind of historical causes or perspectives.His capacity of considering all the points of view, of not closing his historical inquiry to his ideological preferences, and to giving primacy to the historical sources rather than to his personal ideological premises, makes his work well-grounded until today37.A counter example would be the case of Carr, whose History of Soviet Russia has been often criticised because of overlooking Stalinist repression38. And is a precise critique in what he said was an accurate accountant of the development of the Soviet state, he disregarded that crucial point due to a strong ideological bias.Or the case of some ideologically-motivated gender history, that absolutizes ahistorical concepts, such as patriarchy, fitting history into its predetermined framework39. Another example are Foucaultspseudo-historical writings, which are more a kind of philosophical works based on historical examples, where th eory clearly outweighs historical rigor.40 In this cases, the primacy of history is not preserved far from that, it is toughly violated, as is placed at the service of the moral and ideological framework of the writer.We have mentioned as well the issue of categories as a way of implicit moral and ideological judgement. The historian will never get rid of it, but can perfectionate his ability to represent history accurately through them. Lets bring again the example of the category fascist. If the historian is able to understand it properly, and is conscious of all its implications, he will be able to make an appropriate use of it, harmonise to historical standards. Then, if he remains faithful to the sources, would be in the position of identifying fascist movements, or fascist behaviours as were historically understood in the time studied. It will, for example, help him to differentiate it from other kind of authoritarian ideologies, point which is often confused.And this is the way that objectivity should be understood as a capacity of detachment that allows the historian to overcome a fully present-minded and ideological interpretation. And departs from the assertion that primacy must be given to the demands of history, to the guidance of the sources. A way of assessing if this has been achieved is through the test of time the validity of its conclusions through a wide span of time. Quoting again Tosh, is what made him to assert that Hobsbawms Age of Revolution still unsurpassed41, even when Marxism is not anymore seen as a reliable framework of interpretation.All of this can be achievable only if this principle of objectivity is assumed. But it is just a necessary condition, but not sufficient. To accomplish it depends as well on the skill of the historian. But without it, doesnt matter how much skilful the historian is, that his work will not stand the test of time.Along this essay, we have revised some polemic aspects about the historians relationship with his object of study. First of all, after fixing definitions of moral and ideology, we have revised some of the attitudes across the historiography about our topic. Then, through answering to the questions What?, Why? and How? we have explored the relationship between the historian and history, between his perso

No comments:

Post a Comment